Showing posts with label Baroque Literature. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Baroque Literature. Show all posts

Thursday, October 25, 2007

Jonathan Swift (1667-1745)


And he gave it for his opinion, that whoever could make two ears of corn, or two blades of grass, to grow upon a spot of ground where only one grew before, would deserve better of mankind, and do more essential service to his country, than the whole race of politicians put together.

Books from Alibris: Jonathan Swift

Friday, September 21, 2007

Thomas Middleton (1580-1627)

Sierra Club

Quotation

Lands mortgaged may return, and more esteem'd,
But honesty once pawn'd, is ne'er redeem'd.


Books

Please browse our Amazon list of titles about Thomas Middleton. For rare and hard to find works we recommend our Alibris list of titles about Thomas Middleton.

AlibrisResearch

COPAC UK: Thomas Middleton
Library of Canada Search Form
Library of Congress: Thomas Middleton
Other Library Catalogs: Thomas Middleton

Biographical

Thomas Middleton (c.1580-1627) was an English Elizabethan playwright and poet. His best-known plays are The Changeling (written with William Rowley) and Women Beware Women. It is also widely believed that he wrote The Revenger's Tragedy, previously attributed to Cyril Tourneur, and collaborated with Shakespeare on the scenes involving the Weird Sisters and Hecate in Macbeth. Middleton was appointed City Chronologer of the City of London in 1620, a post that he held until his death. His successor in the post was Ben Jonson. [This article is licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License and uses material adapted in whole or in part from the Wikipedia article on Thomas Middleton.]



Books from Alibris: Thomas Middleton

Monday, September 10, 2007

John Locke (1632-1704)

Sierra Club

Quotation

I attribute the little I know to my not having been ashamed to ask for information, and to my rule of conversing with all descriptions of men on those topics that form their own peculiar professions and pursuits.

Books

Please browse our Amazon list of titles about John Locke. For rare and hard to find works we recommend our Alibris list of titles about John Locke.

AlibrisResearch

COPAC UK: John Locke
Library of Canada Search Form
Library of Congress: John Locke
Other Library Catalogs: John Locke

Biographical

English philosopher, was born at Wrington, 10 m. W. of Belluton, in Somersetshire, on the 29th of August 1632, six years after the death of Bacon, and three months before the birth of Spinoza. His father was a small landowner and attorney at Pensford, near the northern boundary of the county, to which neighbourhood the family had migrated from Dorsetshire early in that century. The elder Locke, a strict but genial Puritan, by whom the son was carefully educated at home, was engaged in the military service of the parliamentary party. "From the time that I knew anything," Locke wrote in 1660, "I found myself in a storm, which has continued to this time." For fourteen years his education, more or less interrupted, went on in the rural home at Belluton, on his father's little estate, half a mile from Pensford, and 6 m. from Bristol. In 1646 he entered Westminster School and remained there for six years. Westminster was uncongenial to him. Its memories perhaps encouraged the bias against public schools which afterwards disturbed his philosophic calm in his Thoughts on Education. In 1652 he entered Christ Church, Oxford, then under John Owen, the Puritan dean and vice-chancellor of the university. Christ Church was Locke's occasional home for thirty years. For some years after he entered, Oxford was ruled by the Independents, who, largely through Owen, unlike the Presbyterians, were among the first in England to advocate genuine religious toleration. But Locke's hereditary sympathy with the Puritans was gradually lessened by the intolerance of the Presbyterians and the fanaticism of the Independents. He had found in his youth, he says, that "what was called general freedom was general bondage, and that the popular assertors of liberty were the greatest engrossers of it too, and not unfitly called its keepers." And the influence of the liberal divines of the Church of England afterwards showed itself in his spiritual development.

Under Owen scholastic studies were maintained with a formality and dogmatism unsuited to Locke's free inquisitive temper. The aversion to them which he expressed showed thus - early an innate disposition to rebel against empty verbal reasoning. He was not, according to his own account of himself to Lady Masham, a hard student at first. He sought the company of pleasant and witty men, and thus gaiiied knowledge of life. He took the ordinary bachelor's degree in 1656, and the master's in 1658. In December 1660 he was serving as tutor of Christ Church, lecturing in Greek, rhetoric and philosophy.

At Oxford Locke was nevertheless within reach of liberal intellectual influence tending to promote self-education and strong individuality. The metaphysical works of Descartes had appeared a few years before he went to Oxford, and the Human Nature and Leviathan of Hobbes during his undergraduate years. It does not seem that Locke read extensively, but he was attracted by Descartes. The first books, he told Lady Mashatn, which gave him a relish for philosophy, were those of this philosopher, although he very often differed from him. At the Restoration potent influences were drawing Oxford and England into experimental inquiries. Experiment in physics became the fashion. The Royal Society was then founded, and we find Locke experimenting in chemistry in 1663, also in meteorology, in which he was particularly interested all his life.

The restraints of a professional career were not suited to Locke. There is a surmise that early in his Oxford career he contemplated taking orders in the Church of England. His religious disposition attracted him to theology. Revulsion from the dogmatic temper of the Presbyterians, and the unreasoning enthusiasm of the Independents favoured sympathy afterwards with Cambridge Platonists and other liberal Anglican. churchmen. Whithcote was his favourite preacher, and close intimacy with the Cudworth family cheered his later years. But, though he has a place among lay theologians, dread of ecclesiastical impediment to free inquiry, added to strong inclination for scientific investigation, made him look to medicine as his profession, and before 1666 we find him practising as a physician in Oxford. Nevertheless, although known among his friends as "Doctor Locke," he never graduated in medicine. His health was uncertain, for he suffered through life from chronic consumption and asthma. A fortunate event soon withdrew him from the medical profession.

Locke early showed an inclination to politics, as well as to theology and medicine. As early as 1665 he diverged for a short time from medical pursuits at Oxford, and was engaged as secretary to Sir Walter Vane on his mission to the Elector of Brandenburg. Soon after his return in 1666 the incident occurred which determined his career. Lord Ashley, afterwards first earl of Shaftesbury, had come to Oxford for his health. Locke was introduced to him by his physician, Dr Thomas. This was the beginning of a lasting friendship, sustained by common sympathy with liberty - civil, religious and philosophical. In 1667 Locke moved from Christ Church to Exeter House, Lord Ashley's London residence, to become his confidential secretary. Although he retained his studentship at Christ Church, .and occasionally visited Oxford, as well as his patrimony at Belluton, he found a home and shared fortune with Shafteshury for fifteen years.

Locke's commonplace books throw welcome light on the history of his mind in early life. A paper on the "Roman Commonwealth" which belongs to this period, expresses convictions about religious liberty and the relations of religion to the state that were modified and deepened afterwards; objections to the sacerdotal conception of Christianity appear in. another article; short work is made of ecclesiastical claims to infallibility in the interpretation of Scripture in a third; a scheme of utilitarian ethics, wider than that of Hobbes, is suggested in a fourth. The most significant of those early revelations is the Essay concerning Toleration (1666), which anticipates conclusions more fully argued nearly thirty years later.

The Shaftesbury connexion must have helped to save Locke from those idols of the "Den" to which professional life and narrow experience is exposed. It brought him into contact with public men, the springs of political action and the duties of high office. The place he held as Shaftesbury's adviser is indeed the outstanding circumstance in his middle life. Exeter House afforded every opportunity for society. He became intimate among others with the illustrious Sydenham; he joined the Royal Society and served on its council. The foundation of the monumental work of his life was laid when he was at Exeter House. He was led to it in this way. It was his habit to encourage informal reunions of his intimates, to discuss debatable questions in science and theology. One of these, in the winter of 1670, 15 historically memorable. "Five or six friends," he says, met in his rooms and were discussing principles of morality and religion. They found themselves quickly at a stand by the difficulties that arose on every side. "Locke proposed some criticism of the necessary" limits of human understanding as likely to open a way out of their difficulties. He undertook to attempt this, and fancied that what he had to say might find sufficient space on "one sheet of paper." What was thus begun by chance, was continued by entreaty, written by incoherent parcels, and after long intervals of neglect resumed again as humour and occasions permitted. At the end of nearly twenty years the issue was given to the world as Locke's now famous Essay Concerning Human Understanding.

The fall of Shaftesbury in 1675 enabled Locke to escape from English politics He found a retreat in France, where he could unite calm reflection upon the legitimate operations of "human understanding" with attention to his health. He spent three years partly at Montpellier and partly in Paris. His journals and commonplace books in these years show the Essay in preparation. At Paris he met men of science and letters - Peter Guenellon, the well-known Amsterdam physician; Ole Romer, the Danish astronomer; Thoynard, the critic; Melchisedech Thevenot, the traveller; Henri Justel, the jurist; and Francois Bernier, the expositor of Gassendi. But there is no mention of Malebranche, whose Recherche de la verite had appeared three years before, nor of Arnauld, the illustrious rival of Malebranche.

Locke returned to London in 1679. Reaction against the court party had restored Shaftesbury to power. Locke resumed his old confidential relations, now at Thanet House in Aldersgate. A period of often interrupted leisure for study followed. It was a time of plots and counterplots, when England seemed on the brink of another civil war. In the end Shaftesbury was committed to the Tower, tried and acquitted. More insurrectionary plots followed in the summer of 1682, after which, suspected at home, the versatile statesman. escaped to Holland, and died at Amsterdam in January 1683. In these two years Locke was much at Oxford and in Somerset, for the later movements of Shaftesbury lid not commend themselves to him. Yet the government had their eyes upon him. "John Locke lives a very cunning unintelligible life here," Prideaux reported from Oxford in 1682. "I may confidently affirm," wrote John Fell, the dean of Christ Church, to Lord Sunderland, "there is not any one in the college who has heard him speak a word against, or so much as censuring, the government; and, although very frequently, both in public and private, discourses have been purposely introduced to the disparagement of his master, the earl of Shaftesbury, he could never be provoked to take any notice, or discover in word or look the least concern; so that I believe there is not in the world such a master of taciturnity and passion. Unpublished correspondence with his Somerset friend, Edward Clarke of Chipley, describes Locke's life in those troubled years. It also reveals the opening of his intimate intercourse with the Cudworth family, who were friends of the Clarkes, and connected by birth with Somerset. The letters allude to toleration in the state and comprehension in the church, while they show an indifference to theological dogma hardly consistent with an exclusive connexion with any sect.

In his fifty-second year, in the gloomy autumn of 1683, Locke retired to Holland, then the asylum of eminent persons who were elsewhere denied liberty of thought. Descartes and Spinoza had speculated there; it had been the home of Erasmus and Grotius; it was now the refuge of Bayle. Locke spent more than five years there; but his (unpublished) letters show that exile sat heavily upon him. Amsterdam was his first Dutch home, where he lived in the house of Dr Keen, under the assumed name of Dr Van der Linden. For a time he was in danger of arrest at the instance of the English government. After months of concealment he escaped; but he was deprived of his studentship at Christ Church by order of the king, and Oxford was thus closed against him. Holland introduced him to new friends. The chief of these was Limborch, the successor of Episcopius as Remonstrant professor of theology, lucid, learned and tolerant, the friend of Cudworth, Whichcote. and More. By Limborch he was introduced to Le Clerc, the youthful representative of letters and philosophy in Limborch's college, who had escaped from Geneva and Calvinism to the milder atmosphere of Holland and the Remonstrants. The Bibliotheque universelle of Le Clerc was then the chief organ in Europe of men of letters. Locke contributed several articles. It was his first appearance as an author, although he was now fifty-four years of age. This tardiness in authorship is a significant fact in his life, in harmony with his tempered wisdom.

In the next fourteen years the world received through his books the thoughts which had been gradually forming, and were taking final shape while he was in Holland. The Essay was finished there, and a French epitome appeared in 1688 in Le Clerc's journal, the forecast of the larger work. Locke was then at Rotterdam, where he lived for a year in the house of a Quaker friend, Benjamin Furley, or Furly, a wealthy merchant and lover of books. At Rotterdam he was a confidant of political exiles, including Burnet and the famous earl of Peterborough, and he became known to William, prince of Orange. William landed in England in November 1688; Locke followed in February 1689, in the ship which carried the priri'cess Mary.

After his return to England in 1689 Locke emerged through authorship into European fame. Within a month after he reached London he had declined an offer of the embassy to Brandenburg, and accepted the modest office of commissioner of appeals. The two following years, during which he lived at Dorset Court in London, were memorable for the publication of his two chief works on social polity, and of the epoch-making book on modern philosophy which reveals the main principles of his life. The earliest of these to appear was his defence of religious liberty, in the Epistola de Tolerantia, addressed to Limborch, published at Gouda in the spring of 1689, and translated into English in autumn by William Popple, a Unitarian merchant in London. Two Treatises on Government, in defence of the right of ultimate sovereignty in the people, followed a few months later. The famous Essay concerning Human Understanding saw the light in the spring of 1690. He received funds for the copyright, nearly the same as Kant got in 1781 for his Kritik der reinen Vernunft. In the Essay Locke was the critic of the empirical data of human experience: Kant, as the critic of the intellectual and moral presuppositions of experience, supplied the complement to the incomplete and ambiguous answer to its own leading question that was given in Locke's Essay. The Essay was the first book in which its author's name appeared, for the Epistola de Tolerantia and the Treatises on Government were anonymous.

Locke's asthma was aggravated by the air of London; and the course of public affairs disappointed him, for the settlement at the Revolution fell short of his ideal. In spring, 1691, he took up his residence in the manor house of Otes in Essex, the country seat of Sir Francis Masham, between Ongar and Harlow. Lady Isfasham was the accomplished daughter of Ralph Cudworth, and was his friend before he went to Holland. She told Le Clerc that after Locke's return from exile, " by some considerably long visits, he had made trial of the air of Otes, which is some 20 m. from London, and he thought that none would be so suitable for him. His company," she adds, "could not but be very desirable for us, and he had all the assurances we could give him of being always welcome; but, to make him easy in living with us, it was necessary he should do so on his own terms, which Sir Francis at last assenting to, he then believed himself at home with us, and resolved, if it pleased God, here to end his days as he did. "At Otes he enjoyed for fourteen years as much domestic peace and literary leisure as was consistent with broken health, and sometimes anxious visits to London on public affairs, in which he was still an active adviser. Otes was in every way his home. In his letters and otherwise we have pleasant pictures of its inmates and domestic life and the occasional visits of his friends, among others Lord Peterborough, Lord Shaftesbury of the Characteristics, Sir Isaac Newton, William Molyneux and Anthony Collins.

At Otes he was busy with his pen. The Letter on Toleration involved him in controversy. An Answer by Jonas Proast of Queen's College, Oxford, had drawn forth in 1690 a Second Letter. A rejoinder in 1691 was followed by Locke's elaborate Third Letter on Toleration in the summer of the following year. In 1691 currency and finance were much in his thoughts, and in the following year he addressed an important letter to Sir JohIl Somers on the Consequences of the Lowering of Interest and Raising the Value of Money. When he was in Holland he hac written letters to his friend Clarke of Chipley about the education of his children. These letters formed the substance of the little volume entitled Thoughts on Education (1693), which still hold its place among classics in that department. Nor were the "principles of revealed religion "forgotten. The subtle theological controversies of the 17th century made him anxious to show how simple after all fundamental Christianity is. In the Reasonableness of Christianity as delivered in the Scriptures (anonymous, 1695), Locke sought to separate the divine essence of Christ's religion from later accretions of dogma, and from reasonings due to oversight of the necessary limits of human thought. This intended Eirenicon involved him in controversies that lasted for years. Angry polemics assailed the book. A certain John Edwards was conspicuous. Locke's Vindication, followed by a Second Vindication in 1697, added fuel to this fire. Above all, the great Essay was assailed and often misinterpreted by philosophers and divines. Notes of opposition had been heard almost as soon as it appeared. John Norris, the metaphysical rector of Bemerton and English disciple of Malebranche, criticized it in 1690. Locke took no notice at the time, but his second winter at Otes was partly employed in An Examination of Malebranche's Opinion of Seeing all Things in God, and in Remarks upon some of Mr Norris's Books, tracts which throw light upon his own ambiguous theory of perception through the senses. These were published after his death. A second edition of the Essay, with a chapter added on "Personal Identity," and numerous alterations in the chapter on "Power," appeared in 1694. The third, which was only a reprint, was published in 1695. Wynne's well-known abridgment helped to make the book known in Oxford, and his friend William Molyneux introduced it in Dublin. In 1695 a revival of controversy about the currency diverted Locke's attention. Events in that year occasioned his Observations on Silver Money and Further Considerations on Raising the Value of Money.

In 1696 Locke was induced to accept a commissionership on the Board of Trade. This required frequent visits to London. Meantime the Essay on Human Understanding and the Reasonableness of Christianity were becoming more involved in a wordy warfare between dogmatists and latitudinarians, trinitarians and unitarians. The controversy with Edwards was followed by a more memorable one with Stillingfleet, bishop of Worcester. John Toland, in his Christianity not Mysterious, had exaggerated doctrines in the Essay on Human Understanding, and then adopted them as his own. In the autumn of 1696, Stillingfleet, an argumentative ecclesiastic more than a religious philosopher, in his Vindication of the Doctrine of the Trinity, charged Locke with disallowing mystery in human knowledge, especially in his account of the metaphysical idea of "substance." Locke replied in January 1697. Stillingfleet's rejoinder appeared in May, followed by a Second Letter from Locke in August, to which the bishop replied in the following year. Locke's Third Letter, in which the ramifications of this controversy are pursued with a copious expenditure of acute reasoning and polished irony, was delayed till 1699, in which year Stillingfleet died. Other critics of the Essay on Human Understanding entered the lists. One of the ablest was John Sergeant, a priest of the Roman Church, in Solid Philosophy Asserted Against the Fancies of the Ideists (1697). He was followed by Thomas Burnet and Dean Sherlock. Henry Lee, rector of Tichmarch, criticized the Essay on Human Understanding, chapter by chapter in a folio volume entitled Anti-Scepticism (1702); John Broughton dealt another blow in his Psychologio (1703); and John Norris returned to the attack, in his Theory of the Ideal or Intelligible World (1701 - 1704). On the other hand Locke was defended with vigour by Samuel Bolde, a Dorsetshire clergyman. The Essay on Human Understanding itself was meanwhile spreading over Europe, impelled by the name of its author as the chief philosophical defender of civil and religious liberty. The fourth edition (the last while Locke was alive) appeared in 1700, with important additional chapters on "Association of Ideas" and "Enthusiasm." What was originally meant to form another chapter was withheld. It appeared among Locke's posthumous writings as The Conduct of the Understanding, one of the most characteristic of his works. The French translation of the Essay on Human Understanding by Pierre Coste, Locke's amanuensis at Otes, was issued almost simultaneously with the fourth edition. The Latin version by Richard Burridge of Dublin followed a year after, reprinted it due time at Amsterdam and at Leipzig. In 1700 Locke resigned his commission at the Board of Trade and devoted himself to Biblical studies and religious meditation. The Gospels had been carefully studied when he was preparing his Reasonableness of Christianity. He now turned to the Epistles of St Paul, and applied the spirit of the Essay and the ordinary rules of critical interpretation to a literature which he venerated as infallible, like the pious Puritans who surrounded his youth. The work was ready when he died, and was published two years after. A tract on Miracles, written in 1702, also appeared posthumously. Fresh adverse criticism of the Essay was reported to him in his last year, and the book was formally condemned by the authorities at Oxford. "I take what has been done rather as a recommendation of the book, "he wrote to his young friend Anthony Collins, "and when you and I next meet we shall be merry on the subject. "One attack only moved him. In 1704 his adversary, Jonas Proast, revived their old controversy. Locke in consequence began a Fourth Letter on Toleration. A few pages, ending in an unfinished paragraph, exhausted his remaining strength; but the theme which had employed him at Oxford more than forty years before, and had been a ruling idea throughout the long interval, was still dominant in the last clays of his life.

All the summer of 1704 he continued to decline, tenderly nursed by Lady Masham and her step-daughter Esther. On the 28th of October he died, according to his last recorded words,in perfect charity with all men, and in sincere communion with the whole church of Christ, by whatever names Christ's followers call themselves. "His grave is on the south side of the parish church of High Layer, in which he often worshipped, near the tombs of the Mashams, and of Damaris, the widow of Cudworth. At the distance of 1 m. are the garden and park where the manor house of Otes once stood.

Locke's writings have made his intellectual and moral features familiar. The reasonableness of taking probability as our guide in life was in the essence of his philosophy. The desire to see for himself what is true in the light of reasonable evidence, and that others should do the same, was his ruling passion, if the term can be applied to one so calm and judicial. "I can no more know anything by another man's understanding," he would say, than I can see by another man's eyes. "This repugnance to believe blindly what rested on arbitrary authority, as distinguished from what was seen to be sustained by self-evident reason, or by demonstration, or by good probable evidence, runs through his life. He is typically English in his reverence for facts, whether facts of sense or of living consciousness, in his aversion from abstract speculation and verbal reasoning, in his suspicion of mysticism, in his calm reasonableness, and in his ready submission to truth, even when truth was incapable of being fully reduced to system by man. The delight he took in exercising reason in regard to everything he did was what his friend Pierre Coste remarked in Locke's daily life at Otes. "He went about the most trifling things always with borne good reason. Above all things he loved order; and he had got the way of observing it in everything with wonderful exactness. As he always kept the useful in his eye in all his disquisitions, he esteemed the employments of men only in proportion to the good they were capable of producing; for which cause he had no great value for the critics who waste their lives in composing words and phrases in coming to the choice of a various reading, in a passage that has after all nothing important in it. He cared yet less for those professed disputants, who, being taken up with the desire of coming off with victory, justify themselves behind the ambiguity of a word, to give their adversaries the more trouble. And whenever he had to deal with this sort of folks, if he did not beforehand take a strong resolution of keeping his temper, he quickly fell into a passion; for he was naturally choleric, but his anger never lasted long. If he retained any resentment it was against himself, for having given way to so ridiculous a passion; which, as he used to say, "may do a great deal of harm, but never yet did anyone the least good." Large, round-about common sense, intellectual strength directed by a virtuous purpose, not subtle or daring speculation sustained by an idealizing faculty, in which he was deficient, is what we find in Locke. Defect in speculative imagination appears when he encounters the vast and complex final problem of the universe in its organic unity.

Locke is apt to be forgotten now, because in his own generation he so well discharged the intellectual mission of initiating criticism of human knowledge, and of diffusing the spirit of free inquiry and universal toleration which has since profoundly affected the civilized world. He has not bequeathed an imposing system, hardly even a striking discovery in metaphysics, but he is a signal example in the Anglo-Saxon world of the love of attainable truth for the sake of truth and goodness. "If Locke made few discoveries, Socrates made none." But both are memorable in the record of human progress. In the inscription on his tomb, prepared by himself, Locke refers to his books as a true representation of what he was. They are concerned with Social Economy, Christianity, Education and Philosophy, besides Miscellaneous writings.

Locke on Education

Locke has his place among classic writers on the theory and art of Education. His contribution may be taken as either an introduction to or an application of the Essay on Human Understanding. In the Thoughts on Education imaginative sentiment is never allowed to weigh against utility; information is subordinate to the formation of useful character; the part which habit plays in individuals is always kept in view; the dependence of intelligence and character, which it is the purpose of education to improve, upon health of body is steadily inculcated; to make children happy in undergoing education is a favourite precept; accumulating facts without exercising thought, and without accustoming the youthful mind to look for evidence, is always referred to as a cardinal vice. Wisdom more than much learning is what he requires in the teacher. In instruction he gives the first place to "that which may direct us to heaven," and the second to "the study of prudence, or discreet conduct, and management of ourselves in the several occurrences of our lives, which most assists our quiet prosperous passage through this present life. "The infinity of real existence, in contrast with the necessary finitude of human understanding and experience, is always in his thoughts. This "disproportionateness " between the human mind and the universe of reality imposes deliberation in the selection of studies, and disregard for those which lie out of the way of a wise man. Knowledge of what other men have thought is perhaps of too little account with Locke. "It is an idle and useless thing to make it one's business to study what have been other men's sentiments in matters where only reason is to be judge. "In his Conduct of the Understanding the pupil is invited to occupy the point at which "a full view of all that relates to a question" is to be had, and at which alone a rational discernment of truth is possible. The uneducated mass of mankind, he complains, either "seldom reason at all," or "put passion in the place of reason," or "for want of large, sound round-about sense" they direct their minds only to one part of the evidence, "converse with one sort of men, read but one sort of books and will not come in the hearing of but one sort of notions, and n carve out to themselves a little Goshen in the intellectual world where light shines, and, as they conclude, day blesses them; but the rest of the vast expansion they give up to night and darkness and avoid coming near it." Hasty judgment, bias, absence of an a priori "indifference " to what the evidence may in the end require us to conclude, undue regard for authority, excessive love for custom of mind marked by him as most apt to interfere with the formation of beliefs in harmony with the Universal Reason that is active in the universe. [Adapted from Encyclopedia Britannica (1911)]

Books from Alibris: John Locke

Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz (1646-1716)

Sierra Club

Quotation

There are two kinds of truths: those of reasoning and those of facts. The truths of reasoning are necessary and their opposite is impossible; the truths of fact are contingent and their opposites are possible.

Books

Please browse our Amazon list of titles about Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz. For rare and hard to find works we recommend our Alibris list of titles about Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz.

AlibrisResearch

COPAC UK: Leibniz
Library of Canada Search Form
Library of Congress: Leibniz
Other Library Catalogs: Leibniz

Biographical

German philosopher, scientist, mathematician, diplomat and lawyer. Leibniz constructed the first mechanical calculator capable of multiplication and division. He also introduced the binary number system that is being used in all computers nowadays. Independently of Isaac Newton he 'invented' the infinitesimal calculus. He introduced several notations used in calculus to this day, for instance the integral sign representing an elongated S from the Latin word summa and the d used for differentials from the Latin word differentia. Leibniz thought symbols to be very important for the understanding of things. He also tried to develop an alphabet of human thought, in which he tried to represent all fundamental concepts using symbols and combined these symbols to represent more complex thoughts. Leibniz never finished this. His philosophical contribution to metaphysics is based on the Monadology, which introduces Monads as "substantial forms of being", which are akin to spiritual atoms, eternal, indecomposable, individual, following their own laws, not interacting ("windowless") but each reflecting the whole universe. In the way sketched above the notion of a monad solves the problem of the interaction of mind and matter that arises in Rene Descartes' system, as well as the individuation that seems problematic in Baruch Spinoza's system, which represents individual creatures as mere accidental modifications of the one and only substance. The Theodicee tries to justify the apparent imperfections of the world by claiming that it is optimal among all possible worlds. It must be the best possible and most balanced world, because it was created by a perfect God. [This article is licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License and uses material adapted in whole or in part from the Wikipedia article on Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz.]

Books from Alibris: Leibniz

Tuesday, September 4, 2007

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)

Sierra Club

Quotation

Always recognize that human individuals are ends, and do not use them as means to your end.

Books

Please browse our Amazon list of titles about Immanuel Kant. For rare and hard to find works we recommend our Alibris list of titles about Immanuel Kant.

AlibrisResearch

Lecture: Perpetual Peace
COPAC UK: Immanuel Kant
Library of Canada: Immanuel Kant
Library of Congress: Immanuel Kant
Other Library Catalogs: Immanuel Kant

Biographical

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was a German (Prussian) philosopher, generally regarded as the last major philosopher of the early modern period, and on anyone's account, one of history's most influential thinkers. Kant is most famous for his view--called transcendental idealism--that we bring innate forms and concepts to the raw experience of the world, which otherwise would be completely unknowable. Kant's philosophy of nature and human nature is one of the most important historical sources of the modern conceptual relativism that dominated the intellectual life of the 20th century--though it is likely that Kant would reject relativism in most of its more radical modern forms. Kant is also well-known and very influential for his moral philosophy.

Life

Kant spent most of his life in Konigsberg (now Kaliningrad). He spent much of his youth as a solid but not spectacular student, living more off playing pool than his writings. His revolutionary pieces were written very late in life after a long period of silence.

Kant's philosophy in general

Though he adopted the idea of a critical philosophy, the primary purpose of which was to "critique" or come to grips with the limitations of our mental capacities, Kant was one of the greatest of system builders, pursuing the idea of the critique through studies of metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics.

One famous citation "the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me", sums up his efforts: he wanted to explain in one systematic theory, those two areas or realms. Isaac Newton had developed a theory of physics that Kant wanted to build his philosophy upon. This theory involved the assumpton of natural forces that humans cannot sense, but are used to explain movement of physical bodies.

Kant's metaphysics and epistemology

Kant's most widely read and most influential book is Critique of Pure Reason (1781), which proceeds from a remarkably simple thought experiment. He said, try to imagine something that exists in no time and has no extent in space. The human mind cannot produce such an idea--time and space are fundamental forms of perception that exist as innate structures of the mind. Nothing can be perceived except through these forms, and the limits of physics are the limits of the fundamental structure of the mind. On Kant's view, therefore, there are something like innate ideas--a priori knowledge of some things (space and time)--since the mind must possess these catagories in order to be able to understand the buzzing mass of raw, uninterpreted sensory experience which presents itself to our consciousness. Secondly, it removes the actual world (which Kant called the noumenal world, or noumena) from the arena of human perception--since everything we perceive is filtered through the forms of space and time we can never really "know" the real world.

Kant had wanted to discuss metaphysical systems but discovered "the scandal of philosophy"--you cannot decide what the proper terms for a metaphysical system are until you have defined the field, and you cannot define the field until you have defined the limit of the field of physics first. 'Physics' in this sense means, roughly, the discussion of the perceptible world.

Kant's moral philosophy

Kant develops his moral philosophy in three works: Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals (1785), Critique of Practical Reason (1788) and Metaphysics of Morals (1798). Under this heading Kant is probably best known for his theory about a single, general moral obligation that explains all other moral obligations we have: the categorical imperative. A categorical imperative, generally speaking, is an unconditional obligation, or an obligation that we have regardless of our will or desires. A hypothetical imperative, by contrast, is a conditional obligation, one that we have only if we have some desire or other: if one wants x, one ought to do y.

Our moral duties can be derived from the categorical imperative. The categorical imperative can be formulated in three ways, which he believed to be roughly equivalent (although many commentators do not). The first formulation (the Formula of Universal Law) says: "act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law." The second formulation (the Formula of Humanity) says: "Act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means." The third formulation (the Formula of Autonomy) is a synthesis of the previous two. It says that we should so act that we may think of ourselves as legislating universal laws through our maxims. We may think of ourselves as such autonomous legislators only insofar as we follow our own laws.

The theory that we have universal duties, which hold despite one's subjective (and thus, merely hypothetical) imperatives that seek to fulfill one's own inclinations or happiness instead of these duties, is known as deontological ethics. Kant is often cited as the most important source of this strand of ethical theory (in particular, of the theory of conduct, also known as the theory of obligation.

Further reading

The amount of literature on Kant is ever-growing. Often, the best places to start are the introductions of his translated works. Modern translations usually suggest a variety of secondary literature, the purpose of which is both to explain and to interpret Kant's philosophy. For an example, see Christine Korsgaard's introduction to Mary Gregor's translation of the Groundwork, which not only provides a concise overview of Kant's moral philosophy, but also places his ethics within the framework of the larger critical system.

One of the best pieces of secondary literature on Kant's moral philosophy is a work by Korsgaard called Creating the Kingdom of Ends. In this collection of essays, Korsgaard attempts to organize Kant's ethics into a coherent interpretation that may respond adequately to the modern defenders of ethical systems contrary with Kant's, such as Aristotle's, Hume's, and Hegel's.

Another good starting point of investigation is John Rawls' book of published lecture notes, titled Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy. The work is particularly useful in its investigation of Kant's moral philosophy within the vicissitudes of ethical systems from Hume to Leibniz to Hegel. Two other important scholars of Kant are Henry Allison and Onora O'Neill. Both authors have written books about Kant's moral philosophy. [This article is licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License and uses material adapted in whole or in part from the Wikipedia article on Immanuel Kant.]


Perpetual Peace
Russell McNeil, PhD (Copyright 2005)
[Malaspina Great Books Exclusive]

Immanuel Kant (1724 - 1804), a German (Prussian) philosopher, physicist and theologian by training, is generally regarded as the last major philosopher of the enlightenment and one of the most influential thinkers of modern times.

Kant is most famous for his view, which has come to be know as transcendental idealism--a mode of thinking in which we bring innate forms and concepts--concepts born in the mind--to the raw experience of the world of experience--a world which otherwise would be completely unknowable.

Kant's philosophy of nature and of human nature--and he ties the two together--is one of the most important historical sources of the modern notion of conceptual relativism--a perspective that has dominated the intellectual life of the 20th century--and as we will see in LBST 420 a concept that many people regard as a source of modern alienations--the malaise of modernity. That said, it is likely that Kant would himself would reject this relativistic spin on his philosophy especially in most of its more radical modern forms. The notion of relativism derives from the innate aspect of transcendental idealism.

It works this way. If we accept that real phenomenal knowledge is possible only through the filter of innate--mind born ideas--and appreciate that no two minds are the same--and that therefore no two innate ideas can be identical--then the knowledge that requires illuminate from the innate idea will itself differ--thus, all knowledge must in some degree be relative to these innate suppositions.

Kant himself would likely object to these lines of reasoning because--as is clear from the readings here--that although he believes firmly in what he refers to with undeniable certainty and even inevitability in the Eight Thesis of his Universal History as a hidden plan of nature. Modern relativistic readings of Kant may accept the brilliance of Kant's idea if innate knowledge but reject the certainty of such assertions--for the simple reason that innate reasoning can lead to different conclusions.

Kant's life project might be summed up in one famous citation of his the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me. Kant wanted to explain in one systematic theory, those two areas or realms. Isaac Newton had developed a theory of physics and Kant wanted to build his moral philosophy up from there. This theory of moral philosophy involved the assumption of the existence of certain natural forces akin to the natural forces of Newton but forces that humans cannot sense. From where then does Kant derive the level of moral certainty underpinning these readings?

To answer that question we need to roll back the clock 36 years--to Kant's first major work written at the tender age of 31 in 1755 around the same time as Rousseau's Discourse of last week and only a few decades after Newton's famous Principia. The then obscure Kant's work had an imposing title: Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens: An essay on the Constitution and Mechanical Origin of the Whole Universe According to Newton's Principles.

If recanting was in the cards for Kant--it might have been around the theological and metaphysical inferences he drew from the speculative thesis he offered here. I'll offer you some of the text later and attempt to point out what I mean. And what I mean, what I argue, is that this text exposes Kant's underbelly in ways that are not so obvious in the writing of the mature philosopher.

Kant's grandparents were Scots who immigrated to the Prussian city of Konigsberg. Kant was born there; lived there; attended university there; taught there; and died there at the age of 80. His degree was in theology but he devoted most of his post graduation energies to mathematics and astronomy. Kant's world fame dates from the publication of his Critique of Pure Reason in 1781 when he was 56. The critique is a treatise on the theory of Knowledge and arose out of his interest in Newtonian Physics--the principles of which he believed to be no less true than those of geometry and arithmetic. It was only in these later years that Kant devoted his time to philosophy--in the modern sense of the term--although he did occasionally dabble in science and write an essay on lunar volcanoes in 1785--around the time he wrote these essays here.

The literary style Kant uses in his earlier scientific work is much clearer than in his philosophical works. Kant's objective in writing this book was to extend Newton's philosophy of nature beyond the limits set by Newton which was restricted mainly to the solar system.

Kant's inspiration for this book came from the work of an obscure Englishman named Thomas Wright. Wright had written a work called An Original Theory of the Universe, in which he argued that the sun like the planets in the solar system revolves about some Universal Centre of Gravitation. Furthermore there were throughout the Universe many of such systems--we call these galaxies today.

Kant is concerned with the temporal or evolutionary stages of development of the universe along with its spatial structure: cosmology in other words.

In developing his ideas Kant reaches back as far as the pre-Socratic philosophers Leucippus, Democritus and later to Leucretius and Epicurus to assert that the beginning of creation involved a universal diffusion of primitive matter which helped by gravity or weight brought those elementary pieces together causing vortices.

Kant--unlike the early atomists--was a theist--believing that the universe came into being as an act of creation by a transcendent deity.

Kant thus begins with atoms, a void, Newton's laws and thereby attempts to account for the major stages of the evolutionary development of the cosmos.

But Kant went far beyond anything said by Newton himself who describes the existent regularities found in the world, and especially the solar system--Newton makes no attempt to explain how the system came to be or how it achieved the regularity it now possesses.

Newton's laws account for how the planets remain in their current state but do not account for how they got there. Kant ventured where Newton feared to tread.

He attempted to describe how the galaxies came to be, what spatial and physical distribution they might possess, and what various stages of development they might go through: the universe has history and its stages of development could be traced in terms of well established physical principles.

That the universe is not static and that it undergoes basic change--that it had a history--was a daring and revolutionary assertion. Kant speculated further that the entire universe was constituted of a single unified system in which all these external galaxies participated in motions about a common centre.

He described the exercise initially as … a dangerous expedition ... one in which he has set out... to establish the existence of a supremely wise creator … matter which is the primitive constituent of all things, is therefore bound to certain laws, and when it is freely abandoned to these laws it must necessarily bring forth beautiful combinations. It has no freedom to deviate from this perfect plan. Since matter is subject to a supremely wise purpose, it must necessarily have been put into such harmonious relationships by a first cause ruling over it.

Years later, in the Critique of Pure Reason (1781), Kant would argue that the great problems of metaphysics like the existence of God--are insoluble by scientific thought. But, in the Critique of Practical Reason (1788) he argues that morality requires belief in God's existence. Kant's famous categorical imperative, or absolute moral law, which I'll talk more of in a moment, rests on the same foundation of beauty and purposiveness as the physical world and these are the bridge between the sensible and the intelligible worlds.

So Kant's later writings--at least the ones we are examining here--obscure and soften the bold deistic certitude we hear here with respect to the theological claims. But the certitude he expresses with respect to purpose in the Cosmopolitan essay, for example, seems just as strong.

If the universe is systematic in its structure--a premise Kant seems assured--that systematic structure is evidence of purpose--the working out of a hidden plan.

Taking on the whole universe was for Kant a far easier task than taking on something as simple as say a caterpillar. In the Nebular thesis he says: The origin of the whole present constitution of the universe will become intelligible before the production of a single herb or caterpillar will become distinctly understood ... because of the complications of the manifold constituents.

Kant's intellectual life seems to have been bracketed by an if clause. If ... universe has structure ... then ... purpose is evident.... hidden plan is evident ... If hidden plan is established in the universe writ large, then hidden plans in smaller but more complex systems follow (from caterpillars to human societies) ...

One can only speculate the impact that the subsequent observational confirmation of Kant's speculation in this century might have had on Kant's later intellectual life. With the if clauses less iffy Kant's later reasoning might have been bolder yet.

Kant's most widely read and most influential book is Critique of Pure Reason. It starts with a simple thought experiment. Try to imagine something that exists in no time and has no extent in space. The human mind cannot produce such an idea--time and space are fundamental forms of perception that exist as innate structures of the mind. Nothing can be perceived except through these forms, and the limits of physics are the limits of the fundamental structure of the mind.

We thus have a priori knowledge of some things (space and time)--since the mind must possess these categories in order to be able to understand anything else. For Kant, the actual world--noumenal world--unfiltered by space & time is not really knowable because that world is constantly filtered through the forms of space and time.

Kant is probably best known for his theory about a single, general moral obligation that explains all other moral obligations we have: the categorical imperative. A categorical imperative, generally speaking, is an unconditional obligation, or an obligation that we have regardless of our will or desires. All or moral duties can be derived from the categorical imperative. The categorical imperative can be formulated in three ways:

The first formulation (the Formula of Universal Law) says: act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law. The second formulation (the Formula of Humanity) says: Act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means. The third formulation (the Formula of Autonomy) is a synthesis of the previous two. It says that we should so act that we may think of ourselves as legislating universal laws through our maxims. We may think of ourselves as such autonomous legislators only insofar as we follow our own laws.

A reading of Perpetual Peace requires some understanding of these ideas. It is an essay that takes on the dichotomy between political idealism and political realism. Kant draws heavily upon his critical philosophy to develop a frank analysis of the complexities of politics, weaving together the cynicism of realism and the optimism of idealism. Specifically, the central role he ascribes to liberal republicanism is consistent with a critical perspective where neither principle is effective exclusive of the other. Hs application of various formulations of the Categorical Imperative is shown to lead him to assert the primacy of idealism over realism.

An application of kant's ideas to our responses to 9/11 and the impending attempt to unseat Saddam in Iraq, Kant would agree terror to be order of our day. But while responses we have made and will make may remove individual perpetrators, like bin Ladin and Saddam Hussein, these responses will not secure peace. Kant would agree that evil is undeniable in his world and ours. But its presence in the world is no more proof of its primacy in our nature, or a justification for political cynicism, than the occurrence of illness in a healthy body establishes that the body is inherently unsound and that we should all therefore commit suicide. Evil cannot be a justification for abandoning the dream of peace. In spite of the horrors that plague our world, blunting our moral sensibilities, the human community continues to dream. The appeal of religious and ethical systems for billions of human beings demonstrates the universality of this tendency.

For Kant, the way to peace lies in finding a common ethical basis for communication that would constitute a global identity as humans over and above the completing ties of ethnicity, religion, and nation that separate us.

Kant's essay lies as the base for a strategy that might achieve its ultimate goal: perpetual peace. The way to peace for Kant lies in finding a common ethical basis for communication that would constitute a global identity as humans over and above the completing ties of ethnicity, religion, and nation.

Suggestions for a practical educational programs designed to implement Kant's ideals have included: 1. globally conscious primary and secondary education curricula; 2. cosmopolitan higher education informed by an analytical and empirically based search for common humanity as the necessary ground for empathetic trans-cultural communication; 3 studies on the religious and ethical traditions of the entire world; 4. the creation of global studies curricula with on courses on universal history, economy, politics, and geography; 5. liberal education designed to elevate the vision of humans as moral beings capable of ethical behavior as our essential nature over all racial, national, gender, cultural, and ethnic identities.

Preliminary Articles

1. No Treaty of Peace Shall Be Held Valid in Which There Is Tacitly Reserved Matter for a Future War

Probably not too much difficulty arises here. Tacit means not mentioned. An overarching theme in this essay is the concept of right, a so-called transcendental idea that defies definition--because it is after all outside the box. So, for Kant any agreement on peace that contains an unwritten notwithstanding clause is, by its nature not really a treaty of peace but a suspension of hostilities, a truce.

2. "No Independent States, Large or Small, Shall Come under the Dominion of Another State by Inheritance, Exchange, Purchase, or Donation.

Nations are societies of men--and as such persons not things. To sell, inherit, etc., a state would be to treat the nation as a thing.

3. "Standing Armies (miles perpetuus) Shall in Time Be Totally Abolished

Kant provides a double defense of this idea. One is economic--the maintenance standing armies are more costly than short wars--so wars--where standing armies exist--make economic sense. Besides--and this is a direct application of the Categorical Imperative. The training of soldiers to kill, is to treat a man as a machine--a killing machine--is to treat him as a thing--a means to an end. But men are not to treated as such.

4. National Debts Shall Not Be Contracted with a View to the External Affairs of States.

Kant gives voice here to the enslavement and hostility engendered by the idea of debt. Debt is dangerous--it also enslaves. The prescience of this with respect to the present situation and relationship between the burden of debt carried by third word nations and a correlationship between debt and the rise in international terrorism is interesting. Debt breeds exasperation, despair, and hostility.

5. No State Shall by Force Interfere with the Constitution or Government of Another State.

The non-interference in the internal affairs of foreign states has become an article of international behavior. With any of these articles try substituting neighbor or friend for state. A constitution reflects the common or general will of a society. Forcible interference (direct or implied) with national or personal sovereignty limits and enslaves individuals and states. Nations acting in such a way are treating such states as pawns, or things--this article is again an application of the categorical imperative.

6. No State Shall, during War, Permit Such Acts of Hostility Which Would Make Mutual Confidence in the Subsequent Peace Impossible: Such Are the Employment of Assassins (percussores), Poisoners (venefici), Breach of Capitulation, and Incitement to Treason (perduellio) in the Opposing State.

That war is a sad necessity in the state of nature, Kant accepts. The articles, setting out certain rules of engagement and attempts at setting rules of war have been implemented in modern times. This is a corollary of the first article--for it ensures that a tacit reservation for future war will remain. Dishonorable actions: extermination, assassination, spying (which is direct interference in the internal affairs of another state), flying airplanes into civilian buildings, dropping nuclear weapons onto cities…virtually guarantee that Peace will never be permanent. Nations so offended will bide their time, and peace treaties emerging can never be permanent.

Definitive Articles

The Civil Constitution of Every State Should Be Republican.

Of course Kant means Republican in fact--not in name. Republicanism for Kant is that form of constitution in which the constitution--the law--is owned by and consented to all. The government--the executive--is only the minister. The ruler is but another citizen--not the lawmaker. In a non-republican state--modern Iraq--or wartime Germany-- the will of the executive is the law. Citizens are pawns. Again, the idea here is clearly an application of the categorical imperative--for people are not pawns. Republicanism--as so defined--must reflect the general will: that is it reflects the principle of RIGHT. Everyone in a so-defined constitution is free to do whatever he will--as long as what he wills no wrong.

The Law of Nations Shall be founded on a Federation of Free States.

We are tempted here to see this as a United Nations - A nation of nations. An arrangement whereby all nations alienate their sovereignty--or part of their sovereignty over to a super nation governed by a super ruler. But such an arrangement however determines would contradict the idea of sovereignty. If Canada turns over its sovereignty to a third party--it can no longer claim to be sovereign. This--it can be forcefully argued--is exactly why we had riots in Seattle, and Quebec City. It is at the root of the concern many share around globalization, and free trade. Canada may set rules, but the real power is moving swiftly to multi-nationals. The multi-nationals--the real power behind globalization--act not in the interest of a general will, but a will determined inside the boardrooms of those companies. In its implementation of Bill 28, and other measures The Liberal Government of British Government can be seen as acting as pawns or instruments of this rapidly emerging global reality.

So, whatv does Kant mean by a Federation of Nations? Well he sees it as necessary for peace, because no war can do that--precisely because the victor in war is determined by power. Might does not make right. But the federation is somehow something different than a nation. It is a free association of free states--subject to no binding law. It's a fuzzy sort of idea. Kant admits so. He hints--on the bottom of p.117 that such an association must somehow involve the surrender the right to go to war--which exists in the state of nature. This federation is described there not as a positive idea of a world republic but the negative idea of a federation that prevents war and curbs the tendency to go to war.

Supplements

OF THE GUARANTEE FOR PERPETUAL PEACE

This is where Kant seems to get a bit spooky. Peace is guaranteed not by god, or fate, or providence, or luck--but, by nature! Human purpose ensures peace. He leaves aside the possibility that human purpose is predetermined by providence or god because this theoretical treatise has been crafted by reason--and reason--he admits--has its bounds. Purpose--if I may refer to my opening remarks--can really work only inside the box. Purpose--he seems to imply--is either outside the box--or--part of that noumenal world that we can never really experience because we are restricted to see through the filters of space and time.

It will happen. I'll leave off here.

Books from Alibris: Immanuel Kant

Monday, September 3, 2007

Samuel Johnson (1709-1784)

Sierra Club

Quotation

Don't think of retiring from the world until the world will be sorry that you retire. I hate a fellow whom pride or cowardice or laziness drives into a corner, and who does nothing when he is there but sit and growl. Let him come out as I do, and bark.

Books

Please browse our Amazon list of titles about Samuel Johnson. For rare and hard to find works we recommend our Alibris list of titles about Samuel Johnson.

AlibrisResearch

COPAC UK: Samuel Johnson
Library of Canada: Samuel Johnson
Library of Congress: Samuel Johnson
Other Library Catalogs: Samuel Johnson

Biographical

Dr. Samuel Johnson (1709-1784), often referred to simply as "Dr Johnson", was one of England's greatest literary figures. Although best remembered as the compiler of the first comprehensive English dictionary, Dr Johnson was more than a scholar. Born at Lichfield and educated at Oxford, he moved to London in 1737 with his wife, Tetty, who was twenty years his senior, and began to earn a living as a journalist, whilst working on plays, poetry and biographies. Johnson began his Dictionary of the English Language in 1747, but did not complete it until 1755. It made his name, but not his fortune. Another of his major works, the satire Rasselas (1759), was written specifically to raise money to pay for his mother's funeral. Johnson was at the centre of a literary circle which included such figures as Oliver Goldsmith, Edmund Burke and David Garrick, and founded the Literary Club. In 1763, a young Scottish writer, James Boswell, introduced himself to Johnson. Together they toured the Western Isles of Scotland in 1773, a journey which Johnson immortalised in print. Dr Johnson's last great work was the ten-volume Lives of the English Poets, published between 1779 and 1781. He died in 1784 and is buried in Westminster Abbey. [This article is licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License and uses material adapted in whole or in part from the Wikipedia article on Samuel Johnson.]

Books from Alibris: Samuel Johnson

Sunday, September 2, 2007

Christiaan Huygens (1629-1695)

Sierra Club

Quotation

The world is my country, science is my religion.

Books

Please browse our Amazon list of titles about Christiaan Huygens. For rare and hard to find works we recommend our Alibris list of titles about Christiaan Huygens.

AlibrisResearch

COPAC UK: Christiaan Huygens
Library of Canada: Christiaan Huygens
Library of Congress: Christiaan Huygens
Other Library Catalogs: Christiaan Huygens

Biographical

Christiaan Huygens (born in The Hague on April 14, 1629) was a Dutch mathematician and physicist. He is the son of Constantijn Huygens. In 1655, he discovered Saturn's moon Titan. He also examined Saturn's planetary rings, and in 1656 he found out those rings consisted of rocks. In the same year he observed the Orion Nebula. Using his modern telescope he was able to divide the nebula into different stars. The brighter interior of the Orion Nebula is called the Huygens Region. He also discovered several interstellar nebulas and some double stars. After Blaise Pascal encouraged him to do so, Huygens wrote the first book on probability theory, which was published in 1657. He also worked on the construction of accurate clocks, suitable for naval navigation. In 1658 he published a book on this topic called Horologium. Huygens was elected a member of the Royal Society in 1663. In the year 1666 Huygens moved to Paris where he held a chair at the French Royal Society. Using the Parisian observatory, which was completed in 1672, he made further astronomical observations. He moved back to The Hague in 1681 after serious illness and died there 14 years later on July 8, 1695. [This article is licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License and uses material adapted in whole or in part from the Wikipedia article on Christiaan Huygens.]

Books from Alibris: Christiaan Huygens